The Dictionary of Human Geography

(nextflipdebug2) #1

Comp. by: LElumalai Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_C Date:31/3/09
Time:21:45:56 Filepath://ppdys1108/BlackwellCup/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-
9781405132879/appln/3B2/revises/9781405132879_4_C.3d


positivism, the very philosophy that Popper
thought he had demolished in 1935.
Programmatic statements were made on the
behalf of critical rationalism by some geog-
raphers including Wilson (1972), one of the
key proponents of a scientific approach to
geography during the 1960s, and by Bird
(1975, 1989), and Chouinard, Fincher and
Webber (1984) used Lakatos’ critique and
reformulation of Popper’s proposals to outline
the conduct of research programmes in a nom-
inally scientific human geography. But critical
rationalism was never realized in practice
within geography. Indeed, the very idea of
such anormativephilosophical scheme set
out in advance to generate scientific progress
became increasingly unattractive, especially in
the social sciences, after Kuhn’s (1970 [1962])
writings onparadigms, which stressed the
messiness of scientific practice and the role of
ruptures and revolutions in scientific advance.
Further, as human geography moved towards
postmodernismandpost-structuralismand
their various commitments to anti-realism,
relativismand incommensurability, the pro-
spects of Popper’s critical rationalism gaining
hold in the discipline became ever more
remote. tjb

Suggested reading
Bird (1975). See also Critical rationalism study
page: http://www.geocities.com/criticalrationalist/

critical theory A primarily European tradi-
tion of social and political thought centrally
concerned with critical reflection oncapital-
ismandmodernity. It is closely associated
with the work of the so-called Frankfurt
School, which emerged in Germany in the
1920s. The School formed amidst the defeat
of left-wing parties in western Europe, the
degeneration of the Russian revolution into
Soviet Stalinism and the rise offascism. The
members of the School expanded classical
marxism, drawing upon ideas from Freud,
Weber and others outside the Marxist trad-
ition, and in particular sought to supplement
the orthodox focus onpolitical economy
with concepts drawn from the spheres of aes-
thetics, culture andphilosophy. Its key mem-
bers were Theodor Adorno (1903–69), Max
Horkheimer (1895–1973) and Herbert
Marcuse (1898–1979); another scholar asso-
ciated with the School, Walter Benjamin
(1892–1940), committed suicide fleeing
Nazi-occupied France. By then, most mem-
bers of the School had already moved to the
USA, returning to Germany in the 1950s. The

key postwar representative of critical theory is
Ju ̈rgen Habermas (1929– ).
Horkheimer (1975) defined critical theory
in contrast to traditional theory (the neutral,
objective stance claimed in the natural sci-
ences). Unlike traditional theory, critical social
theory had to be reflexive and account for its
own social origins and purposes. Its attitude
was one of distrust towards the social rules
and conventions encountered by individuals
in their daily lives. The critical theorists
identified new trends in capitalism with the
emergence of monopolies, the closer associ-
ation of state and capital, the growth of
bureaucracy, and the rationalization of social
life linked to the dominance of instrumental
reason. They explored issues of identity,
authoritarianism, the spread of commodity
production, reification andalienation. They
were concerned with the way in whichcul-
turehad become an industry, with popular
cultural forms serving to distract workers
from the increasingly repetitive nature of
their daily work, thus promoting a sense of
fatalism and blocking the potential for resist-
ance. Their conclusions on the ideological
barriers to revolution in an increasingly one-
dimensional society tended to confirm a logic
of domination that led to a pessimistic political
immobility that they found it difficult to break
out of.
Ju ̈rgen Habermas has carried on the tradi-
tion of critical theory in the postwar period,
but has also modified it in important ways. His
early work presents a theory ofknowledge-
constitutive interests (technical, practical and
emancipatory) that guide different types of
science – empirical–analytical, hermeneutic
and critical (Habermas, 1987). Here, critical
theory takes on the role of a therapeutic cri-
tique, modelled on Freudianpsychoanalytic
theoryand directed towards freeing society
from ideologically distorted perceptions.
Problems with this formulation led
Habermas to take an important ‘communica-
tive turn’ in the formulation of critical theory
in the 1970s (Habermas, 1984, 1987). Social
life requires co-operative, communicative
interaction and Habermas undertakes the
‘rational reconstruction’ of the underlying sys-
tem of rules that speakers must master in order
to communicate. Speakers uttering a sentence
necessarily (though usually implicitly) make
certain validity claims (to truth, rightness,
sincerity, intelligibility). A genuine rational
consensus on the basis of these validity claims
can emerge only under conditions of free
and unconstrained debate that Habermas

Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_C Final Proof page 125 31.3.2009 9:45pm

CRITICAL THEORY
Free download pdf