The Dictionary of Human Geography

(nextflipdebug2) #1

Comp. by: LElumalai Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_C Date:31/3/09
Time:21:45:52 Filepath://ppdys1108/BlackwellCup/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-
9781405132879/appln/3B2/revises/9781405132879_4_C.3d


markets were serially and coextensively disem-
bedded from, and re-embedded in, social
institutions and relations. In particular, the
possibility of a counter-hegemony to the self-
regulating market resided in the resistance to
(and reaction against) the commodification of
the three fictitious commodities – land, labour
and money – that represented the spontaneous
defence of society.
Marx’s account identifies a fundamental
contradiction at the heart of capitalism – a
contradiction between two great classes
(workers and owners of capital) that is funda-
mentally an exploitative relation shaped by the
appropriation of surplus. Unlikefeudalism,in
which surplus appropriation is transparent (in
the forms of taxes and levies made by land-
owners and lords, backed by the power of the
church and Crown), surplus value is obscured
in the capitalistlabour process. Marx (1967)
argues that labour is the only source of value
and value is the embodiment of a quantum of
socially necessary labour. It is the difference
between the sale of a worker’s labour power
and the amount of labour necessary to repro-
duce it that is the source of surplus value. The
means by which capital extracts this surplus
value under capitalism – through the working
day, labour intensification and enhancing
labour productivity – coupled to the changing
relations between variable and constant capital
determine, in Marx’s view, the extent, degree
and forms of exploitation. In the first volume
ofCapital, Marx identifies the origins of sur-
plus value in the organization of production
(the social relations of production so-called).
In volume II, Marx explains how exploitation
affects the circulation of capital, and in
volume III he traces the division of the total
product of exploitation among its beneficiaries
and the contradiction so created. In Marxist
theory two kinds of material interests – inter-
ests securing material welfare and interests
enhancing economic power – are linked
through exploitation (exploiters simultan-
eously obtain greater economic welfare and
greater economic power by retaining control
over the social allocation of surplus through
investments). Members of a class, in short,
hold a common set of interests and therefore
have common interests with respect to the
process of exploitation (see alsomarxism).
In the wake of Marx’s work, the central
debates over capitalist exploitation have turned
on (i) whether the labour theory of value is a
necessary condition for any truth claim about
exploitation, (ii) whether exploitation can be
made congruent with the complex forms of

class differentiation associated with modern
industrial society, and (iii) whether there are
non-Marxist accounts of exploitation. Inneo-
classical economics, for example, exploit-
ation under capitalism is seen as ‘the failure
to pay labour its marginal product’ (Brewer,
1987, p. 86). Exploitation in this view is
micro-level and organizational. That is to say,
using micro-economic theory exploitation is a
type of market failure due to the existence of
monopoly or monopsony. In more developed
versions of this organizational view, exploit-
ation can be rooted in extra-market forces;
for example, free-riding or asymmetric
information (the so-called principal–agent
problem). A more structural account of
exploitation from a liberal vantage point
would be the ideas of Henry George or John
Maynard Keynes, for whom land owners or
rentier classes (non-working owners of finan-
cial wealth) produce not exploitation in the
Marxist sense, but exploitation as waste and
inefficiency due to ‘special interests’.
In the Marxian tradition, there has been in
general an abandonment of the labour theory
of value – away from the view of Elster (1986)
that ‘workers are exploited if they work longer
hours than the number of hours employed in
the goods they consume’ (1986, p. 121) –
towards John Roemer’s notion that a group is
exploited if it has ‘‘some conditionally feasible
alternative under which its members would be
better off’ (Roemer, 1986a, p. 136). Perhaps
the central figure in developing these argu-
ments is Erik Olin Wright (1985), who sought
to account for the contradictory class location
of the ‘middle classes’ (in that they are simul-
taneously exploiters and exploited). Building
on the work of Roemer, Wright distinguishes
four types of assets, the unequal control or
ownership of which constitute four distinct
forms of exploitation under capitalism: labour
power assets (feudal exploitation), capital
assets (capitalist exploitation), organization
assets (statist exploitation) and skill assets
(socialist exploitation). While pure modes of
production can be identified with single forms
of exploitation, ‘actually existing capitalism’
consists of all four, opening up the possibility
of the simultaneous operation of exploiter/
exploitee relations (e.g. managers are capital-
istically exploited but are organizational
exploiters).
A long line of Marx-inspired theorizing
has attempted to grasp the relations between
(European or transatlantic) capitalism,empire
and the non-capitalist (or developing) world.
This is the heart of theories ofimperialism

Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_C Final Proof page 61 31.3.2009 9:45pm

CAPITALISM
Free download pdf