The History of Mathematics: A Brief Course

(coco) #1

  1. HELLENISTIC GEOMETRY 323


prism required the least material to enclose a given volume, out of all the possible

prisms whose base would tile the plane.^3

Analysis, locus problems, and Pappus' theorem. Book 7 of the Synagoge is a trea-

sure trove of fascinating information about Greek geometry for several reasons.

First, Pappus describes the kinds of techniques used to carry on the research that

was current at the time. He lists a number of books of this analysis and tells who

wrote them and what their contents were, in general terms, thereby providing valu-

able historical information. What he means by analysis, as opposed to synthesis,

is a kind of algebraic reasoning in geometry. As he puts it, when a construction is

to be made or a relation is to be proved, one imagines the problem to have been

solved and then deduces consequences connecting the result with known principles,

after which the process is reversed and a proof can be synthesized. This process

amounts to thinking about objects not yet determined in terms of properties that

they must have; when applied to numbers, that process is algebra.

Second, Book 7 also contains a general discussion of locus problems, such as we

have already encountered in Apollonius' Conies. This discussion exerted a strong

influence on the development of geometry in seventeenth-century France.

Proposition 81 of Euclid's Data, discussed above, inspired Pappus to create a

very general proposition about plane loci. Referring to the points of intersection of

a set of lines, he writes:

To combine these discoveries in a single proposition, we have writ-

ten the following. If three points are fixed on one line... and all

the others except one are confined to given lines, then that last one

is also confined to a given line. This is asserted only for four lines,

no more than two of which intersect in the same point. It is not

known whether this assertion is true for every number.

Pappus could not have known that he had provided the essential principle by

which a famous theorem of projective geometry known as Desargues' theorem (see

Section 2 of Chapter 12) was to be proved 1400 years later. Desargues certainly

knew the work of Pappus, but may not have made the connection with this theorem.

The connection was pointed out by van der Waerden (1963, p. 287).

Pappus discusses the three- and four-line locus for which the mathematical

machinery is found in Book 3 of Apollonius' Conies. For these cases the locus is

always one of the three conic sections. Pappus mentions that the two-line locus

is a planar problem; that is, the solution is a line or circle. He says that a point

satisfying the conditions of the locus to five or six lines is confined to a definite

curve (a curve "given in position" as the Greeks said), but that this curve is "not

yet familiar, and is merely called a curve." The curve is defined by the condition

that the rectangular parallelepiped spanned by the lines drawn from a point to

three fixed lines bears a fixed ratio to the corresponding parallelepiped spanned by

the lines drawn to three other fixed lines. In our terms, this locus is a cubic curve.

(^3) If one is looking for mathematical explanations of this shape, it would be simpler to start with
the assumption that the body of a bee is approximately a cylinder, so that the cells should be
approximately cylinders. Now one cylinder can be tightly packed with six adjacent cylinders of
the same size. If the cylinders are flexible and there is pressure on them, they will flatten into
hexagonal prisms.

Free download pdf