The Spartan Regime_ Its Character, Origins, and Grand Strategy - Paul Anthony Rahe

(Dana P.) #1

62 Polıteía


One would be hard put to charge John Stuart Mill with being a partisan


of Sparta. Lacedaemon was, in his view, “memorable for the peculiar pettiness


of its political conduct.” Furthermore, Mill gave great emphasis to the fact


that, when temporarily liberated from supervision by his fellow citizens, a


Spartan “was not only the most domineering and arrogant, but in spite of, or


rather by a natural reaction from his ascetic training, the most rapacious and


corrupt of all Greeks.” And yet, despite the distaste that he consistently dis-


played, the great nineteenth-century liberal could not help being moved by


“the steadiness of the Spartan polity, and the constancy of Spartan maxims.”


He was even prepared to acknowledge that the “habitual abnegation of or-


dinary personal interests, and merging of self with an idea”—so evident at


Lacedaemon—“were not compatible with pettiness of mind. Most of the an-


ecdotes and recorded sayings of individual Lacedaemonians breathe a certain


magnanimity of spirit.” To these concessions, Mill ultimately added another


of equal or even greater importance: “There is indeed no such instance of


the wonderful pliability, and amenability to artificial discipline, of the human


mind, as is afforded by the complete success of the Lacedaemonian legislator,


for many generations, in making the whole body of Spartan citizens at Sparta


exactly what he had intended to make them.”^70


Aristotle shared Mill’s misgivings. Like Xenophon, who conveyed his


criticism by indirection, and like Plato, who was forthright, the peripatetic


thought it morally obtuse and politically imprudent that the Spartan lawgiver


had designed the Lacedaemonian regime for the cultivation of martial virtue


almost to the exclusion of all other forms of excellence. The Spartans he bluntly


accused of having turned their children into wild animals, and their polity’s


dramatic decline in his own time he traced to the fact that the Spartiates had


not been properly instructed in the refined use of leisure and in pursuits suited


to times of peace.^71 But, like Xenophon, Plato, and Mill, Aristotle nonetheless


admired the achievements of early Lacedaemon. Although, as we shall see, he


was not among those who believed that everything attributed by tradition to


Lycurgus was actually his work, he was nonetheless prepared at times to speak


as if this were so. This composite, quasi-fictional figure he ranked as one of


“the best lawgivers,” alongside Solon and Charondas. He drew attention to


the fact that Lycurgus had transformed a tyranny into an aristocracy, and he


praised him for having been almost alone in making provision for the paıdeía


and moral formation of the citizens of the political community within which


he lived. In his treatise on the polıteía of the Lacedaemonians, Aristotle ap-

Free download pdf