MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
216 Aristotle and his school

the animal kingdom, in particular for his philosophical anthropology, and

to what extent the description of these bodily structures and processes is

guided by teleological concerns. However, such a study would have to take

into account the different levels of explanation on which Aristotle is at work

in various contexts as well as thetypesof context in which Aristotle expresses

himself on these issues. The following typology of contexts (which does

not claim to be exhaustive) would seem helpful:

( 1 ) First, there are contexts in which Aristotle explains the bodily struc-

tures with a view to their suitabilityK

#
!#0 

!#Lfor the


fulfilment of the psychic functions in which they are involved, for exam-

ple, when he describes the structure of the human hand by reference to the

purpose it is intended to serve,^35 or man’s upright position with a view to

man’s rational nature.^36 This is because he believes that a purely material

description of the bodily structures would be just as insufficient as a purely

formal description of soul functions, because it ignores the suitability of

these structures for the exercise of the powers for the sake of which they

exist and with a view to which they are shaped. As G. E. R. Lloyd sum-

marises: ‘whenever he is dealing with an instrumental part that is directly

concerned with one of the major faculties of the soul identified in theDe

anima, Aristotle cannot fail to bear in mind precisely thatthatis the func-

tion that the part serves, and he will indeed see the activities in question as

the final causes of the parts’.^37 However, as Lloyd himself recognises, this

is just one of several concerns Aristotle has in the zoological works, and it

is not consistently implemented.

( 2 ) Secondly, there are contexts in which the ‘mechanics’ of psychic

processes are discussed in physiological terms. Thus in his explanations

of memory, recollection, sleeping and dreaming, Aristotle goes into great

(though not always clear) physiological detail to describe the bodily parts

involved in these ‘psychic’ activities and the physical processes that accom-

pany them (e.g. the discussion of the ‘bodily imprints’ in memory,^38 or of

the ‘reactivation’ of sense-movements in sleep due to the withdrawal of the

blood).^39 As I have tried to show elsewhere, these discussions deal with op-

erations of the sensitive (and perhaps also the intellectual) part of the soul

under rather special circumstances, but they also have important implica-

tions for the physiology ofnormalsense-perception (on which the relevant

sections inOn the SoulandOn Sense Perceptionare rather uninformative).^40

(^35) Part. an. 687 b 6 ff. (^36) Part. an. 686 a 27 ff. (see below); cf. alsoIA 706 a 19.
(^37) Lloyd ( 1992 ) 149. (^38) Mem. 450 a 27 ff. (^39) Insomn. 459 b 7 ff.; 461 b 11 ff.
(^40) See van der Eijk ( 1994 ) 75 – 87.

Free download pdf