Teaching Critical Thinking in Psychology: A Handbook of Best Practices

(ff) #1

213


Teaching Critical Thinking About Difficult Topics


the examples used to teach critical thinking skills focus too strongly on evaluations of the


findings of formal research, students will learn to apply their critical thinking skills to such


evaluations, but not to their other beliefs. In this situation, we will have provided students


with a way to reject whatever formal research challenges their unfounded prior beliefs


without teaching them to also evaluate those prior beliefs: We will have taught them to


defend their personal prejudices against reasonable and well-founded objections.


Whenever we teach students skills, it is important to teach explicitly about the condi-


tions of applicability as well. In the case of critical thinking skills, failure to do so raises the


risk of a very undesirable outcome.


Teaching Students to Evaluate Their Personal Experience-Based Beliefs

Including personal experience-based beliefs as targets of critical thinking practice examples


does not guarantee that students will apply those skills to their personal experience-based


beliefs. Students expect to learn to critique research and the media and are proud to


recognize deliberate scams, for example. They may be considerably more resistant to the


suggestion that they apply critical thinking skills to their own beliefs, particularly those


formed on the basis of personal experience, and they often find ways to avoid changing


their beliefs regardless of the amount and quality of evidence presented (Chinn & Brewer,


1993, 1998). Among the factors that determine how strongly people hold and value beliefs


is the extent to which those beliefs participate in our explanations of the events we see in


the world around us (Anderson, Lepper, & Ross, 1980; Preston & Epley, 2005; Slusher &


Anderson, 1996). The belief that personal experience has a special epistemological status


is fairly central to how most people understand the world (Trosset, 1998). Furthermore,


the belief that personal experience is epistemologically unique is reinforced by cultural


norms, and often even by formal education.


Carey and Smith (1993) suggested that the assumption about the unique power of


personal experience forms part of a “common-sense epistemology” (p. 237). They propose


that persons holding such an epistemology are unaware of the role of theoretically tainted


interpretation in the establishment of beliefs and, instead, they “see knowledge arising


unproblematically (and directly) from sensory experiences and see knowledge as simply the


collection of many true beliefs” (p. 237). If students believe that particular beliefs come


directly from sensory experience, they will not consider it necessary to evaluate those beliefs.


If we insist that they evaluate those beliefs, we challenge not just the beliefs, but also the


students’ common-sense epistemology. Making changes to that basic epistemological


assumption requires students to make changes to their system of beliefs as a whole.


To what extent is the “common-sense epistemology” correct? Clearly students don’t


need research or critical thinking to evaluate the beliefs that, for example, they have two


children or drive a used car. But they may assume for the same reason—their personal


experience—that the belief that they have precognitive dreams is also outside of the


domain of research and critical thinking. They may respond to our insistence that they


think critically about the evidence for precognitive dreams the same way they would


respond if we insisted that they think critically about how many children they have or


whether they drive a used car.

Free download pdf