Jewish Philosophical Politics in Germany, 1789-1848

(Amelia) #1

298 } Notes to Chapter 2



  1. In PR § 270 , Hegel states that religion is a foundation for the state only insofar as
    religion has truth as its content, and that, even then, it is only a foundation (Grundlage) and
    not yet the state’s realized Sittlichkeit. On Hegel’s understanding of religion as a foundation
    of the state, see Franco, Hegel’s Philosophy of Freedom, 296 – 306.

  2. Hegel, Vorlesungen über Rechtsphilosophie (the Ilting edition), 1 : 293.

  3. Ibid.

  4. “On the contrary, the development of this Idea has established the truth [of the prop-
    osition] that spirit, as free and rational, is inherently (an sich) ethical, that the true Idea is
    actual rationality, and that it is this rationality which exists as the state. It has further emerged
    just as plainly from this Idea that the ethical truth which it embodies is present for thinking
    consciousness as a content on which the form of universality has been conferred—that is,
    law—and that the state in general knows its ends, and recognizes and implements them with
    a determinate consciousness and in accordance with principles” (Hegel, PR § 270 ).

  5. Ibid. Hegel is here railing not against “polemical” forms of Protestantism but against
    the illegitimate, irrational authority of the Catholic Church. He adds parenthetically: “In
    Protestantism, there is no laity, so that there is likewise no clergy to act as an exclusive depos-
    itary of church doctrine”—in other words, Protestantism does not infantilize its adherents,
    who are permitted and expected to think for themselves.

  6. Ibid.

  7. Franco, Hegel’s Philosophy of Freedom, 328.

  8. Hegel, PR § 270. For Hegel, art and religion are also forms of knowing, but not cogni-
    tive, scientific knowing, not knowing als ein Gedachtes.

  9. Hegel’s position on Jewish assimilation, however, does not necessarily vitiate the
    interpretations of those who see Gans’s Hegelian vision as striking a balance between in-
    tegration and the assertion of a form of particularity. (See, for example, Livné-Freudenthal
    [“Kultur als Weltanschauung,” 65 ], Schorsch [TC, 216 ], or Waszek [“Hegel, Mendelssohn,
    Spinoza,” 197 ].) Jewish Hegelians’ visions of Jews within a differentiated Sittlichkeit should
    not be assumed to be identical to Hegel’s.

  10. Hegel, PR § 270. Wood identifies Friedrich Schlegel as the defender of the idea of
    the “Christian state” whom Hegel “seems to have in mind here” (ibid., editor’s footnote 12 ).

  11. Ibid., § 270.

  12. Ibid. Hegel also writes: “Instead of mastering one’s opinions by the labour of study
    and subjecting one’s volition to discipline so as to elevate it to free obedience, the easiest
    course is to renounce cognition of objective truth, to nurse a sense of grievance and hence
    also of self-conceit, and to find in one’s own godliness all that is required in order to see
    through the nature of the laws and of political institution, to pass judgment on them, and
    to lay down what their character should and must be. And indeed, since these are the find-
    ings of a pious heart, they must be infallible and indisputable; for if we make religion the
    basis of our intentions and assertions, these cannot be faulted on account of either their
    shallowness or their injustice (Unrechtlichkeit)” (ibid.). Wood identifies Fries as the target of
    Hegel’s polemic here (ibid., editor’s footnote 5 ).

  13. Ibid, § 270.

  14. Laurence Dickey underscores the social thrust of Hegel’s Protestantism as a political
    ideology and shows that Hegel’s “Protestantism” was in fact directed against the Ortho-
    dox Protestantism of 1820 s Prussia, which Hegel saw as mired in narrowly subjectivist faith

Free download pdf