MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
Aristotle on the matter of mind 215

the position of women, or on the natural disposition of the good citizen).

Moreover, he also seems to recognise that natural dispositions, though being

necessary conditions for the realisation of human moral and intellectual

capacities, are notsufficientto provide human beings with virtue and with

happiness, but need development, training, and education.^30 To be sure, he

recognises the existence of ‘natural virtues’K

 " L,^31 but they are


in need of regulative principles (such as ‘prudence’,!#

Lin order to


develop in the right direction, and they are even potentially harmful without

these regulative principles, as his discussion of ‘shrewdness’K

!#L


shows.^32 Thus in the sphere of such distinctly human things as virtue, he

acknowledges that nature requires further elaboration and even correction

by ‘art’K#L. There is a tension here between a ‘biological’ and an

‘ethical’, perhaps ‘anthropocentric’ approach to human activity which has

been well expressed by Gigon in his discussion of Aristotle’s treatment of

the contribution of nature to human happiness in the first chapter of the

Eudemian Ethics: ‘In the background lurks the problem (which is nowhere

explicitly discussed in the Corpus Aristotelicum as we have it) why nature,

which arranges everything for the best, is not capable of securing happiness

for all people right from the start.’^33

To summarise this first section: a comprehensive study of Aristotle’s views

on the bodily structures and processes involved in the actualisation of the

various psychic functions of organisms (nutrition, growth and decay, lo-

comotion, sense-perception, desire, imagination, thinking) would be very

desirable.^34 Such a study would be even more interesting if it could demon-

strate to what extent these views are determined by a concern, on his part,

to provide a physical foundation for his normative views on hierarchy in

(^30) See the discussion inEth. Nic. 2. 1 , esp. 1103 a 24 : ‘Therefore virtues occur neither naturally nor
contrary to nature, rather they occur to us because we are naturally suited to receive them and to
bring them to perfection by habituation’ (&’' -
& 1 R
 
/ " 0
"1  !
. 8  D
( 0  
  . 
1 $ , and 10. 9 , esp. 1179 b
21 ff.; cf. alsoEth. Eud. 1. 1.
(^31) Eth. Nic. 1144 b 15 – 16 and b 35 ff.
(^32) Eth. Nic. 1144 a 24 ff., b 3 , 9.
(^33) Gigon ( 1971 ) 108 : ‘Im Hintergrund lauert das Problem (das in unserem corpus Aristotelicum nirgends
expressis verbis verhandelt wird), warum die-
, die doch alles1 3 <
einrichtet,
nicht in der Lage ist, alle Menschen von vorneherein mit der Eudaimonie auszustatten.’
(^34) This is not to deprecate the importance of, indeed my indebtedness to, existing scholarship on this
topic. Extremely useful (and deserving to be taken into account much more thoroughly by students
of Aristotle’s psychology) are the contributions by Tracy ( 1969 ); and by Solmsen ( 1950 ), esp. 464 ff.,
( 1955 ), ( 1957 ), ( 1961 a), and ( 1961 b). Nor are some German contributions from the nineteenth century
to be neglected, such as Baumker ( ̈ 1877 ); Neuh ̈auser ( 1878 a, b); Schmidt ( 1881 ); Kampe ( 1870 ); Schell
( 1873 ). Still useful are Beare ( 1906 ); R ̈usche ( 1930 ); and Peck ( 1953 ). See further Manuli and Vegetti
( 1977 ); Webb ( 1982 ); G. Freudenthal ( 1995 ) and Sisko ( 1996 ) 138 – 57.

Free download pdf